Peter GrünwaldRamifications and sufficient causes. |
c-fcs-98-42 [original] [abstract] |
[mail to author] [mail to moderator] [debate procedure] [copyright] |
You mentioned in your talk that Lin's use of the mnemonic "causes"
tends to be misleading. I agree with this, and indeed the observation
from our group to his work was that it was more or less a reformulation
of what had already been done using occlusion. However, I wonder
if there isn't a similar problem with your use of the mnemonic "do".
When you characterize the
A1. Peter Grünwald (19.2):
Yes and no. `Yes' in the sense that the word `Do' may be misleading too
- - indeed, nobody needs to be doing something when a coin falls on the
table. `No' in the sense that I am very explicit in my article about the
`physics' of Do: I state precisely what has to happen in a domain in
order for
Namely,
Lin's use of the predicate
In other words, we do not really know what we are trying to model by the
predicate
References:
c-tark-96-51 | Judea Pearl. Causation, Action, and Counterfactuals. Proc. Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, 1996, pp. 51-73. |
C1-1. Erik Sandewall (21.2):
Peter,
You wrote
... I am very explicit in my article about the `physics' of Do:
I state precisely what has to happen in a domain in order for
|
The ternary predicate
|
Erik
References:
c-ijcai-95-1985 | Fangzhen Lin. Embracing Causality in Specifying the Indirect Effects of Actions. [postscript] Proc. International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 1995, pp. 1985-1991. |
C1-2. Peter Grünwald (23.2):
The difference is that it is not clear what exactly has to happen (in
the real world) for a fluent
For example,
is how Lin formalizes the suitcase domain. This translates to `if both switches of the famous suitcase are up, then it is caused to be open'
But is the suitcase caused to be open by the mere fact that the switches are up? Shouldn't it rather be: `the suitcase is caused to be open only if the the switches are put in the up position? One may argue about this - as one may argue about the appropiateness of lots and lots of uses of the word `caused' in everyday language: in different situations the word can stand for different things. Because of this ambiguity, I argue, theories of action in which `caused' is used as an atomic concept, intended to be used whenever we use the word `caused' in everyday language, will run into trouble at some point.
I think the concept of `intervention' suffers no such ambiguity. Suppose
I give you a description of the complete state of a reasoning domain at
time
C1-3. Vladimir Lifschitz (25.2):
In connection with Lin's suitcase example, Peter Grünwald asks:
Is the suitcase caused to be open by the mere fact that the switches are up?
Shouldn't we rather say that the suitcase is caused to be open if the
the switches are put in the up position?
|
In our official theories of causation we typically suppose that all
causal relations must be between discrete events ordered sequentially
in time. For example, the shooting caused the death of the victim.
Certainly, many cause and effect relations are like that, but by no
means all. Look around you at the objects in your vicinity and think
of the causal explanation of the fact that the table exerts pressure
on the rug. This is explained by the force of gravity, but gravity
is not an event. Or think of the solidity of the table. It is
explained causally by the behavior of the molecules of which the
table is composed. But the solidity of the table is not an extra
event, it is just a feature of the table.
|
C1-4. Fangzhen Lin (25.2):
I was delighted and flattered, on the one hand, to learn that one of my previous work had been the focus of discussions in recent Newsletters on Reasoning about Actions and Changes. On the other hand, I was also disappointed and disturbed that much of the remarks about my work were either based on unsubstantiated claims (see below) or plain personal insults such as Peter Grünwald's indignity "`I know what I'm modelling' whereas Lin does not." Hey man, are you really that desperate that you could not find any other way to defend your work?
I don't think this is what this newsletter was set up for, and I'm sure this is definitely not what this community needs.
to be misleading. I agree with this, and indeed the observation from our
group to his work was that it was more or less a reformulation of what
had already been done using occlusion. However, I wonder if there isn't a
|
- Fangzhen Lin
References:
c-ijcai-95-1985 | Fangzhen Lin. Embracing Causality in Specifying the Indirect Effects of Actions. [postscript] Proc. International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 1995, pp. 1985-1991. |
C1-5. Erik Sandewall (25.2):
Peter, Vladimir, and Fangzhen
(The following combines answers to your respective comments to the discussion)
A common feature in much of the recent work is the use of an operator
that "enables" change, that is, the operator excepts a feature from
the requirement or the preference of persistence. The neutral term exception
operator then covers both occlusion (often written as a predicate
Anyway, when such logics are used and one is to express that a certain "cause" has a certain "effect", then one has in principle three possibilities:
Peter, you seem to argue that (3) is the right approach, and quote Fangzhen as using (1); Vladimir defends this with the reference to Searle. However, I observe that in his 1995 article, Fangzhen allows both (1) and (3). The general form of causal rules in his formula (16) allows one or more uses of the exception operator in the antecedent. However, example (22) does not use it, apparently in order to assure that the minimization will be computable by Clark completion. Isn't that a problem in your (Peter's) case as well?
Vladimir, I don't see why everything that's called "causation" in natural language has to be handled with the same logical devices. Seconding Peter's point of view, why can't we use one formalization for causation chains, where one change causes another change, and another formalization for static dependencies? The causal propagation semantics that I introduced in my KR 1996 paper [c-kr-96-99] and used for assessments of several approaches to ramification, is exactly a way of formalizing those cases where one change causes another. The kinds of situations that Searle refers to, or the early "dumbbell" example of Ginsberg and Smith represent arguably another class of phenomenona.
For causal propagation of change, there remains the choice between approaches (2) and (3) above: should the rule trigger on the fact that change actually occurred, or on the fact that change was enabled? This is important especially when actions are nondeterministic.
In the Features and fluents tradition, we first used alternative (3) (tech reports only), but then two group members, Tommy Persson and Lennart Staflin argued that (2) was the right way to go. Their paper at ECAI 1990, [c-ecai-90-497], uses (2) for characterizing indirect change. Their paper contains examples from continuous domains, but the formalism is also defined for, and applies equally well to the discrete case. (A revised version of the paper [r-linkoping-90-45] extends the work) In their approach, they wrote rules where the antecedent requires a specific fluent to actually have changed its value, but they also allowed to specify or to restrict the new or the old value.
We were not alone, of course. The paper by del Val and Shoham at IJCAI '93,
[c-ijcai-93-732] defines a predicate
some further requirements are needed in order to ensure that the
extension of
|
Finally, in order to answer Vladimir's question
Can you please explain this?
|
... the observation from our group to [Lin's] work was that it was
more or less a reformulation of what had already been done using
occlusion
|
By my understanding of "reformulation", I'm expecting at least
something like:
|
... we argue that normal state constraints that refer only to the
truth values of fluents are not strong enough for [specifying the
effects of actions using domain constraints], and that a notion of
causation needs to be employed explicitly.
|
Technically, we introduce a new ternary predicate...
|
Here
|
Using this predicate, we can represent fluent-triggered [causal
statements]
|
Besides the material that is mentioned in the abstract, the paper also contains a section 4, which begins
The procedure we followed in solving the suitcase problem can be
summarized as follows: ...
|
We should of course not get enmeshed in priority debates, neither in this Newsletter nor anywhere else. I do feel however that many papers in our area get published with very incomplete accounts of previous and related work. This is unlikely to change because of the constraints that affect us all: limitations on our time, and on the number of pages allowed for each article. No reason to cast stones, therefore, but maybe the section on "related work" in research papers ought not to be our only mechanism for assembling topic-specific surveys and bibliographies, and possibly the present debate forum could serve as a complement. Additional contributions are invited to this account of recent history, therefore.
References:
c-ecai-90-497 | Tommy Persson and Lennart Staflin. A Causation Theory for a Logic of Continuous Change. Proc. European Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 1990, pp. 497-502. Also available as Linköping technical report Nr. 90-18 [postscript]. |
c-ictl-94-82 | Patrick Doherty and Witold Lukaszewicz. Circumscribing Features and Fluents. Proc. International Conference on Temporal Logic, 1994, pp. 82-100. |
c-ijcai-93-732 | Alvaro Del Val and Yoav Shoham. Deriving Properties of Belief Update from Theories of Action (II). Proc. International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 1993, pp. 732-737. |
c-ijcai-95-1985 | Fangzhen Lin. Embracing Causality in Specifying the Indirect Effects of Actions. [postscript] Proc. International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 1995, pp. 1985-1991. |
c-kr-89-137 | Hector Geffner. Default Reasoning, Minimality and Coherence. Proc. International Conf on Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 1989, pp. 137-148. |
c-kr-96-87 | Joakim Gustafsson and Patrick Doherty. Embracing Occlusion in Specifying the Indirect Effects of Actions. Proc. International Conf on Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 1996, pp. 87-98. |
c-kr-96-99 | Erik Sandewall. Assessment of ramification methods that use static domain constraints. [entry] Proc. International Conf on Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 1996, pp. 99-110. |
j-jlc-4-581 | Erik Sandewall. The Range of Applicability of some Non-monotonic Logics for Strict Inertia. Journal of Logic and Computation, vol. 4 (1994), pp. 581-615. |
mb-Sandewall-94 | Erik Sandewall. Features and Fluents. The Representation of Knowledge about Dynamical Systems. Oxford University Press, 1994. |
r-linkoping-90-45 | Persson and Lennart Staflin. Cause as an Operator in a Logic with Real-valued Fluents and Continuous Time. Appeared as Linköping technical report Nr. 90-45 [postscript]. |
C1-6. Peter Grünwald (27.2):
Vladimir,
I agree with you that the concept of `causality in terms of intervention only' is too narrow (and Searle expresses it quite well!); I just think that most of the examples in common sense reasoning we are currently dealing with are simple enough to be formalized in `interventionistic' terms.
On the technical side, I do think there are some advantages in using
the formalization one would obtain by translating the `reverse switches
domain' (example 5 in my paper) to the suitcase domain, i.e. using
These advantages are the same as those outlined for the switches domain in my common sense paper (see example 5).
C1-7. Peter Grünwald (27.2):
Fangzhen,
First of all, let me apologize. I am very sorry to have insulted you with my remarks. This was never my intention. Too eager to write a reply quickly, I wrote it without thinking and I didn't realize that it would be taken literally.
In fact, I find your approach one of the most intuitive I have come across; I think we both have quite similar intuitions about we are modelling which makes it all the more silly to write `you don't know what you're modelling'. Here is what I really wanted to say; I hope I'll be able to formulate it in a better way now:
`I think it is clearer what kind of situation can and what kind of situation cannot be modeled with the help of the `Do' predicate (which is intended to stand for interventions) than with the help of the `Caused' predicate (which, if I understand you correctly, is intended to be used in those situations in which we would use the word Caused in natural language).'
Now that I'm at it, let me elaborate on this a little bit:
Though their roots are different (`Do' coming from Pearl's structural equation theory and `Caused' coming from your work), it turns out that formally speaking, `Do' is almost the same as your `Caused' : they are defined in very similar ways which may even be equivalent (though this hasn't been proven). One of the aims of (the long version of) my paper is to point this out. That it may make sense to point it out can be seen from example 5 in the paper (the `reversed switches domain', originally due to Sandewall and/or Doherty, I believe). The Do-predicate occurs there in the following axiom:
Do(Light(t), TRUE) ·-> Do(Switch(t), TRUE) | (*) |
If we describe to one another, in natural language, what is modelled by this axiom, then we would probably not use any causal terms (does putting on the light cause the switch to be on?) (see the paper for details). However, (*) can be modelled equally well by your `caused'-predicate as with the `do'-predicate used here. It follows that your `caused'-predicate has broader applicability than it might seem, which I think is worth noting.
Peter
C1-8. Peter Grünwald (27.2):
Erik,
You wrote:
Peter, you seem to argue that (3) is the right approach, and quote
Fangzhen as using (1); Vladimir defends this with the reference to
Searle. However, I observe that in his 1995 article, Fangzhen allows
both (1) and (3). The general form of causal rules in his formula
(16) allows one or more uses of the exception operator in the
antecedent. However, example (22) does not use it, apparently in order
to assure that the minimization will be computable by Clark completion.
Isn't that a problem in your (Peter's) case as well?
|
C1-9. Vladimir Lifschitz (27.2):
Erik,
I am puzzled by your comments about Lin's predicate
You quote from Lin's abstract:
Technically, we introduce a new ternary predicate...
|
Compare e.g. my article in Journal of Logic and Computation, vol. 4, no. 5, 1994, section 7.2 (misprint corrected): |
Here |
This reduces to
|
First, if
Second, Lin's paper and yours use different temporal formalisms. To compare the two approaches, let's translate your formulas into the situation calculus. The counterpart of the formula
(s, t]Xp ^ [t]p = F |
Ab(p, a, s) ^ Value(p, Result(a, s)) = F | (1) |
¬ Ab(p, a, s) ·-> Value(p, Result(a, s)) = Value(p, s) |
Lin's IJCAI-95 paper was a major development that has not been fully appreciated so far by the nonmonotonic community.
--Vladimir
C1-10. Erik Sandewall (27.2):
Vladimir,
I thought I had found a previously unused term when I used "exception operator" as a generic for "occlude", "release", "Caused", etc. I don't think you would claim that all of those are trivially reducible to abnormality?
Re
First, if |
When I referred to the special case of
Re
The fundamental difference between (1) and |
The translation task is actually
very simple, since my formalism allows for both linear
time and branching time (F&F page 138 ff). For branching time,
the notation
(t-, t] Xp ^ [t] p = F | (1) |
Caused(p, F, t) | (2) |
[t-, t] p := F |
C1-11. Fangzhen Lin (27.2):
Erik,
Some thoughts about your note C1-5.
1.
2.
Caused(p, true, s) =/= Occlude(p, s, s) ^ H(p, s) | ||
Caused(p, true, s) =/= Occlude(p, s) ^ H(p, s) |
3. Regarding the previous results of occlude that you mentioned:
... we argue that normal state constraints that refer only to the truth values of fluents are not strong enough for [specifying the effects of actions using domain constraints], and that a notion of causation needs to be employed explicitly. |
See e.g. the Persson-Staflin paper at ECAI 1990. Several papers in
our group during 1988-1993 used a unique concept, "occlusion" or
"explanation" of change for several purposes: for imprecise timing
of changes within an action with extended duration, for nondeterminism,
and also for "our intuition that a discontinuity should have a cause"
(Persson/ Staflin). The abstract continues:
|
4. Regarding the connection between your PMON and the minimization strategy that I used, yes, I'd be the first to admit that they are very similar. I apologize for not knowing it earlier. Thinking back, it's not surprising how they come together. As you know, I have been a devotee of what you call "filtered preferential entailment" approach for as long as I can remember, going back when Yoav and I were working on our provably correct theories of actions.
The idea of minimizing
5. I enjoyed reading Gustafsson and Doherty's KR'96 paper. I learned a lot
from that paper. Patrick and I had some correspondences on the related
topics. I believe we found some common grounds, but none in terms of
"one can be reformulated in terms of another". (Patrick, correct me if
I'm wrong.) If anything, I wouldn't call PMON(RCs) a "trivial extension
of PMON to causal rules", especially when
Last but not the least, Erik, I have all the respects and regards in the world for you and your work! And Peter, there is no hard feeling whatsoever.
C1-12. Murray Shanahan (12.3):
Erik,
Also, I imagine that the event calculus is now able to represent these
things, and it would be interesting to hear what the history was there
(Murray? Rob?).
|
The issue of ramifications and indirect effects is dealt with quite thoroughly in my book Solving the Frame Problem, especially in the context of the event calculus. (Incidentally, the book also deals extensively with the situation calculus, so it's not just an axe-grind for a particular formalism.) A large number of standard benchmark scenarios are discussed. These include the following.
I believe the treatment of these scenarios covers all the issues in the current debate. (One version of Thielscher's circuit example raises some interesting issues not covered in the book. But this example can be dealt with too.)
In particular, the event calculus formalism presented in the book incorporates a Releases predicate, much like Vladimir's releases predicate and Erik's occlusion, which exempts a fluent from the common sense law of inertia. (The intellectual debt is duly acknowledged in the book.) It also permits state constraints, such as
HoldsAt(Alive, t) |
as well as more "causal" constraints such as,
Initiates(a, Wet, t) |
If anyone has a scenario they think the book's formalism can't handle I'd like to hear from them.
I do feel however that many papers in our
area get published with very incomplete accounts of previous and related
work.
|
This is unlikely to change because of the constraints that affect
us all: limitations on our time, and on the number of pages allowed
for each article.
|
Murray
Vladimir Lifschitz, in reply to Erik Sandewall (ENRAC 27.2 (98022)), asks the following:
First, if
|
In fact, one can make a case that any change must involve instantanous
changes. Consider the classical example of two adjacent intervals meeting
at timepoint
For what its worth, by the way, this is one of the few places where quantum physics seems to agree with naive intuition :-)
Pat Hayes
Q2. Camilla Schwind (21.2):
As far as I have understood your approach, you do not use a causality
predicate (or connective), but rather you define a causality
relationship or causal implication by means of material implication as
(6)
and
(3)
But then you can derive classically,
Does you approach behave in this way and do you think that causality should rather be non-monotonic?
A2. Peter Grünwald (23.2):
Yes, my `causal implication' is monotonic. To handle examples like
Shoot ^ ¬ -loaded ·-> Do(Alive(1), False) |
Shoot ^ -Abnormali ·-> Do(Alive(1), False) |
C3-1. Vladimir Lifschitz (21.2):
Hi Erik,
You mentioned in your talk that Lin's use of the mnemonic "causes" tends
to be misleading. I agree with this, and indeed the observation from our
group to his work was that it was more or less a reformulation of what
had already been done using occlusion.
|
Regards, Vladimir
C3-2. Erik Sandewall (25.2):
See comment C1-5 above.
This on-line debate page is part of a discussion at recent workshop; similar pages are set up for each of the workshop articles. The discussion is organized by the area Reasoning about Actions and Change within the Electronic Transactions on Artificial Intelligence (ETAI).
To contribute, please click [mail to moderator] above and send your question or comment as an E-mail message.